This is a blog about economics, history, law and other things that interest me.
Tuesday, December 12, 2017
Friday, December 8, 2017
Hartman on Public Choice
Andrew Hartman has an essay at The Baffler arguing that “libertarianism is a political philosophy
shot through with white supremacy. Public choice theory, a technical language
nominally about human behavior and incentives, helps ensure that blacks remain
shackled.”
I have pointed out before that I am not a libertarian. I
have been critical of libertarians on several occasions (for instance, here
and here)
. I am not associated with George Mason, not paid by the Koch brothers, and not
really a big fan of James Buchanan. So why bother writing this? I do have an
interest in public choice, and I find the recent attempts to bind racism,
Buchanan, public choice, libertarianism, and the Koch brothers into a neat little bundle ridiculous.
Below are quotes from Hartman’s essay (in bold) and my
responses to them.
IN DECEMBER 1992, AN
OBSCURE ACADEMIC JOURNAL published an article by economists Alexander
Tabarrok and Tyler Cowen, titled “The Public Choice Theory of John C. Calhoun.”
Tabarrok and Cowen, who teach in the notoriously libertarian economics
department at George Mason University, argued that the fire-breathing South
Carolinian defender of slaveholders’ rights had anticipated “public choice
theory,” the sine qua non of modern libertarian political
thought.
That obscure academic journal is The Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics. While it
may not be The Baffler, it has been
around for over 150 years, and Nobel prize winners, such as Oliver Williamson,
Douglass North and Ronald Coase have published in it.
Public choice theory,
which grew in stature across the late twentieth century and is now a bedrock
conservative doctrine marketed to right-wing policymakers by the billionaire
Koch brothers, has indeed tilted the scales of justice in favor of the white,
rich, and powerful.
Libertarians seem unaware that Buchanan’s public choice
theory is the thing without which their philosophy cannot exist. Milton
Friedman does not refer to Buchanan or public choice in Capitalism
and Freedom. Robert Nozick does not mention Buchanan or public choice in Anarchy,
State and Utopia. David Boaz can put
together a 600 page Libertarian
Reader that has just a handful of references to public choice and no
readings from Buchanan or Tullock. On a personal note, I was once invited to a
lunch where John Allison former head of BB&T and a well-known libertarian
spoke. I remember him talking a lot about Aristotle, but I don’t recall any mention
of Buchanan or any other public choice theorists. I’m not suggesting that there
are not libertarians who like Buchanan’s work, but I don’t see a case for the
claim that it is regarded as an essential ingredient.
In marking Calhoun’s
political philosophy as the crucial antecedent of public choice theory,
Tabarrok and Cowen unwittingly confirmed what critics have long maintained:
libertarianism is a political philosophy shot through with white supremacy.
Public choice theory, a technical language nominally about human behavior and
incentives, helps ensure that blacks remain shackled.
Cowen and Tabarok did not mark Calhoun as a crucial
antecedent of public choice. To the contrary, they argue that economists have
ignored Calhoun. It would be more accurate to say that they argue that although
Calhoun did not influence the development of public choice theory, there are
some interesting similarities. They note some of these similarities, but also
point to significant differences. Including the differences that enabled him to
include support for slavery in his philosophy.
The sheer volume and
intensity of these protests suggest that MacLean’s observations have hit a
nerve. And by historicizing the putatively neutral and scientific character of
Buchanan’s research, MacLean has apparently shaken the pediment supporting the
altar of this libertarian saint.
Apparently, Hartman regards it as noteworthy that calling
someone’s friend a racist would strike a nerve. I’m not sure what to make of
that. As for neutral. I don’t know of anyone who would argue that Buchanan’s
work was neutral. Buchanan had values that he argued for throughout his career.
There is just no evidence that racism was one of them.
Just as Calhoun
developed his novel political philosophy in response to the growing fear among
his class of southern slaveholders that a Northern majority might seek to
abolish slavery, Buchanan’s public choice theory was an innovative approach to
resisting federal enforcement of civil rights in the South.
Hartman simply parrots MacLean here. They use innuendo to
create a link between Buchanan and segregation, while ignoring the well
documented intellectual context in which Buchanan was working. Buchanan was one
of a number of people in the 1950s and 1960s working on applying economic or
rational choice methods to the analysis of politics.
Buchanan saw his work as part of this broader movement. The
following quotes are from a talk
he gave on public choice theory at Hillsdale College in 2003
“Public choice should be understood as a research program
rather than a discipline or even a subdiscipline of economics. Its origins date
to the mid-20th century, and viewed retrospectively, the theoretical “gap” in
political economy that it emerged to fill seems so large that its development
seems to have been inevitable. Nations emerging from World War II, including
the Western democracies, were allocating between one-third and one-half of
their total product through political institutions rather than through markets.
Economists, however, were devoting their efforts almost exclusively to
understanding and explaining the market sector.” He goes on to explain that he “entered
this discussion with a generalized critique of the analysis generated by the
Arrow Black approach.” He also describes the 19th century thinker
who influenced his work. No, it was not Calhoun. It was Knut Wicksell.
Oddly, Hartman cites S.M.
Amadae, but seems to have missed Amadae’s description of this broader
context, Amadae describes Buchanan’s early essays as responses to the work of
Ken Arrow and his Calculus of Consent
(with Gordon Tullock) as “a new analysis of the rapidly forming study of
politics that had been articulated by John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern,
Duncan Black, Arrow, and Arrow’s student Anthony Downs.” (Amadae 136)
Buchanan was part of a movement to develop a rational choice
approach to politics. He also had normative views about what government should
do. These beliefs were essential to James Buchanan, but not central to public
choice. Being interested in a rational
choice approach to politics does not require that one hold any specific set of
normative beliefs. A rational choice approach to politics has been followed by
people as disparate views of what should be as James Buchanan, Amartya Sen,
Howard Rosenthal and Jon Elster.
Other people involved in the development of a rational
choice approach to politics, such as Anthony
Downs, Amartya
Sen and Mancur
Olson, also viewed Buchanan’s work as part of this broader movement and
engaged his arguments in their work.
If Hartman is right, then he and MacLean have seen through a
false facade that fooled all of these other scholars. Buchanan somehow managed
to hide his true motives from all of them, tricking them into believing that,
like them, he was trying to understand
collective decision making, when in fact he was simply working to preserve race
based segregation.
As opposed to wishing
to free the masses from a state controlled by the capitalist elite, Buchanan wished
to free the capitalist elite from a state controlled by the unruly masses. And
this returns us, suitably enough, to John C. Calhoun.
Public choice theory is interesting and important because recognizing
that the state is composed of human beings means that the state can be
controlled by an elite that oppresses the masses or a majority that oppresses a
minority. The outcome depends upon the
institutions for making public choices. Some of us hope that it is possible to
have institutional arrangements that protect the majority from a despotic elite
and protect minorities from the tyranny of the majority.
In the end, there is no evidence for Hartman’s argument and
considerable evidence against it. Public choice theory did not develop out of
the work of Calhoun nor was it an outgrowth of attempts to preserve segregation
in Virginia. Buchanan was influential in the development of public choice, but public
choice theory is not synonymous with the thought of James Buchanan. Buchanan and public choice theory are not the
sine qua non of modern libertarianism. In fact there is no necessary connection
between public choice and any set of normative beliefs.
In the end, I am puzzled why Hartman would choose to write
an essay about something that he obviously has so little interest in? He doesn’t
appear to have made any attempt to learn anything about the history of public
choice theory beyond reading MacLean. He
could have written a better informed essay if he had read the Wikipedia page on
public choice.
Wednesday, November 15, 2017
Some Recent Podcasts
If you are interested in the economy of colonial America
listen to two recent episodes of Liz Covart’s Ben Franklin’s World: The Revolutionary Economy and The Politics of Tea. Of course, the politics of tea is
about the economics of tea.
If you want to know about the economic divergence between
Western Europe and the Middle East listen to Jared Rubin discuss his recent
book on Garreth Petersen’s Economics
Detective.
If, on the other hand, you are interested in listening to
two intellectual historians who do not know anything about public
choice theory discuss a book about public choice theory by another intellectual
historian who does not know anything about public choice theory you should definitely
check out Andrew Hartman and Ray Haberski discussing Nancy McLean’s Democracy
in Chains on
Trotsky and the Wild Orchids
Monday, November 13, 2017
New Books in Economic and Business History
The Business History Conference's blog The Exchange has a list of new and forthcoming books in economic and business history. There are several that I am looking forward to reading
Anne Fleming, City of Debtors: A Century of Fringe Finance (Harvard University Press, December 2017)
Douglas A. Irwin, Clashing over Commerce: A History of US Trade Policy (University of Chicago Press, November 2017)
Naomi R. Lamoreaux and John Joseph Wallis, eds., Organizations, Civil Society, and the Roots of Development(University of Chicago Press, December 2017)
Qian Lu, From Partisan Banking to Open Access: The Emergence of Free Banking in Early Nineteenth Century Massachusetts (Palgrave, October 2017)
Laura Philips Sawyer, American Fair Trade: Proprietary Capitalism, Corporatism, and the 'New Competition,' 1890–1940(Cambridge University Press, December 2017)
Anne Fleming, City of Debtors: A Century of Fringe Finance (Harvard University Press, December 2017)
Douglas A. Irwin, Clashing over Commerce: A History of US Trade Policy (University of Chicago Press, November 2017)
Naomi R. Lamoreaux and John Joseph Wallis, eds., Organizations, Civil Society, and the Roots of Development(University of Chicago Press, December 2017)
Qian Lu, From Partisan Banking to Open Access: The Emergence of Free Banking in Early Nineteenth Century Massachusetts (Palgrave, October 2017)
Laura Philips Sawyer, American Fair Trade: Proprietary Capitalism, Corporatism, and the 'New Competition,' 1890–1940(Cambridge University Press, December 2017)
Thursday, October 26, 2017
Business History's Introspective Mood
Business history appears to be in an introspective mood.
Business
History Review has a special issue on debating methodology in business
history.
The latest issue of Business History
examines the role of narrative in business history.
In First View at Enterprise
and Society you can find Water Friedman’s talk “Recent Trends in Business History:
Capitalism, Democracy, and Innovation” from the meeting of the Business
History Conference.
In general, business history seems to be an unusually
introspective field.
The introduction to the special issue of Business History Review,
for instance, provides this list of recent work on methodology in business
history:
“Recent examples
include Naomi R. Lamoreaux, “Reframing the Past: Thoughts about Business
Leadership and Decision Making under Uncertainty,” Enterprise & Society 2,
no. 4 (2001): 632–59; Mary O’Sullivan and Margaret B. W. Graham, “Moving
Forward by Looking Backward: Business History and Management Studies,” Journal
of Management Studies 47, no. 5 (2010): 775–90; Geoffrey Jones and Walter A.
Friedman, “Business History: Time for Debate,” Business History Review 85, no. 1
(2011): 1–8; Daniel M. G. Raff, “How to Do Things with Time,” Enterprise &
Society 14, no. 3 (2013): 435–66; Matthias Kipping and Behlül Üsdiken, “History
and Organization Studies: A Long-Term View,” in Organizations in Time: History,
Theory, Methods, ed. Marcelo Bucheli and R. Daniel Wadhwani (New York, 2014),
33–55; Abe de Jong, David Michael Higgins, and Hugo van Driel, “Towards a New
Business History?” Business History 57, no. 1 (2015): 5–29; Stephanie Decker,
Matthias Kipping, and Daniel Wadhwani, “New Business Histories! Plurality in
Business History Research Methods,” Business History 57, no. 1 (2015): 30–40;
and Christina Lubinski and Daniel Wadhwani, “Reinventing Entrepreneurial
History,” Business History Review (forthcoming).”
Monday, September 25, 2017
New History of Capitalism meets the History of Economic Thought
Jonathan Levy has a paper forthcoming in Business History Review, “Capital
as Process and the History of Capitalism.” If you have access to the
journal it is available on First View. He attempts to develop a definition of
capital that is useful for the study of capitalism. I should be grading papers
right now so I will make this quick.
Unfortunately, it bears many of the hallmarks of some of
the most celebrated work in the new history of capitalism.
1. Misunderstanding basic economics: Here for, for instance, is
his description of the problems associated with thinking of capital as a
produced means of production
And yet, because it
equates capital with a produced physical factor of production, the materialist
conception is a highly restrictive definition of capital. For the writing of
history, there are chiefly three almost natural consequences of the materialist
restriction. First, because of its emphasis on a produced factor of physical
production, capital becomes almost synonymous with industrial machinery and
equipment. Second, likewise the materialist capital concept abstracts from
money—treating monetary and financial dynamics as extrinsic to both capital and
the “real economy” in general. Third, for reasons to be explained later, the materialist
capital concept is a temporally static concept. Thus, in addition to money it
also abstracts from historical time—or at least, in pursuit of analytical
clarity, it abstracts from the many eventful historical processes that are
extrinsic from the point of view of the physical characteristics of the masses
of objects that materialists define as capital.
Reference to a principles of economics textbook would have
made clear that capital is not synonymous with industrial machinery and
equipment.
2. Use of sources that can at best be described as sloppy. I
have been interested in Veblen since I was an undergraduate. Levy seems
interested in Veblen as well. When I checked the places where
Levy specifically quotes Veblen this is what I found. Levy is in bold
“At the most abstract
level, capital, in this line of thought, is what Thorstein Veblen once called a
“pecuniary magnet.”11 (Levy page 5)
“11
Thorstein B. Veblen, “On the Nature of Capital II: Investment, Intangible
Assets, and the
Pecuniary Magnate,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 23, no. 1
(1908): 104–36.”
One might think that Veblen used the phrase “pecuniary
magnet” in this paper. He did not. He did use the phrase “pecuniary magnate.”
But a magnate is not a magnet. Veblen is referring to people, “captains of
industry,” not capital. If Veblen ever referred to capital as a pecuniary
magnet it was not in the cited paper.
Oddly enough, Berch Berberoglu made this same mistake earlier this year. Since neither references the other one has to conclude that they made the mistake independently.
“By becoming the
exclusive legal owners of capitalized goods, capitalists over time had
politically and legally “cornered” the market in immaterial “technological
expedients.”42” (Levy page 14)
“42 Thorstein B. Veblen, “Fisher’s Capital and Income,” Political
Science Quarterly 23, no. 1 (1908): 117.”
Again, one might think that the quoted phrases appear on page 117; they do not. Like “pecuniary magnet” they do not appear anywhere in the
paper.
“Addressing culture, Veblen argued that
capital was merely one economic “method of
doing things” in the
world among others.44” (Levy page 14)
“44 Thorstein
B. Veblen, “Why Is Economics Not an Evolutionary Science?” Quarterly Journal of Economics 12, no. 4 (1898): 389.”
Levy is at least in the ballpark this time. Veblen uses the
phrase “methods of doing things.” He does not, however, use it on page 389.
Page 389 is devoted to his critique of the hedonistic conception of man, not an
argument that capital was merely one economic method of doing things.
“If capital has no fixed,
authentic value, the question becomes, as Veblen put it, “Whose imputation of
value is to be accepted?”71 (Levy page 20)
“71 Veblen,
“Fisher’s Capital and Income,” 120.”
This time Levy almost nailed it. The quote is in the paper,
and he only missed the citation by 5 pages; its on page 125.
At what point does putting quotation marks around things
that were not a actually said by the person they are attributed to become a
problem in historical scholarship.
Sunday, September 3, 2017
I Blame Foner
The author in New York Times
By
the Book today was Jesmyn Ward, author of Sing, Unburied, Sing and Salvage
the Bones
These are her answers to two of the questions:
What’s the last great book you read?
“The Half Has Never Been Told: Slavery and the Making of
America Capitalism,” by Edward E. Baptist. It taught me so much about slavery
and how slavery enabled America to become America. Every time I left my house
after reading it, I saw the world differently. I saw the legacy of human misery
underpinning it all.
What’s the most interesting thing you learned from a book
recently?
From “The Half Has Never Been Told”: “All told, more than
$600 million, or almost half of the economic activity in the United States in
1836, derived directly or indirectly from cotton produced by the million-odd
slaves — 6 percent of the total U.S. population — who in that year toiled in
labor camps on slavery’s frontier.”
In other words, the most interesting thing she has learned
from a book recently is an inaccurate assessment of the role of slavery in the American
economy that was
concocted in Ed Baptist’s imagination and presented in one of the worst
books by an academic historian that I have ever read.
I blame Eric Foner. Foner is not the only one to blame, but
he certainly deserves a large share of the blame.
Foner praised the book in The New York Times and did not point out that Baptist
was simply making things up. Foner is a famous historian with a long record of
impressive scholarship. It is not unreasonable for non-historians to place
their faith in his assessments of work in American history. We all count on
recognized experts to give us some guidance in areas that are beyond our
personal expertise. Foner, however, failed them. He took a shot at economists,
repeated Baptist’s misleading historiography, and failed to note the
fundamental flaws in the book.
The flaws truly are fundamental. The claim that slavery was
the driving force behind American economic development was central to Baptist’s
book. I have seen the book cited on this point by numerous people. Yet Baptist
did not actually estimate the importance of slavery; he did not even try. He
made a up some numbers, added them up and compared them to an actual estimate of GDP.
The way he added up the numbers did not make sense. He is clearly unfamiliar with
the problem of double counting or the difference between the sales of newly
produced goods and the sales of assets. Even if he had looked in a principles of
economics textbook to learn the basics of national income accounting, however, it would not have solved the fundamental problem: he was just making up the numbers. Non-historians
are likely say to themselves, “These numbers must be okay; it was reviewed by famous
historians, like Eric Foner, and they did not say anything.” Eric Foner, however, does not have that
excuse. Nor do other historians who refused to call bullshit on Baptist. Foner
owed the readers of the New York Times
a critical reading of the book, and he let them down. Personally, I think this
unwillingness to call bullshit on other historians, just because you like their
conclusions, is a serious threat to the integrity of history.
As for me, as long as people keep citing his book, I will
keep pointing out that Baptist is a charlatan.
Friday, September 1, 2017
Economic History to Read, Listen and Watch
Read:
Victoria Bateman on Why
bigger states are more progressive
Listen:
Gregory Clark on Rationally
Speaking on What
Caused the Industrial Revolution? (and the why it is so difficult to answer
that question)
Noel Johnson at the Economics
Detective on The
French Revolution, Property Rights and the Coase Theorem
Watch:
Alan Taylor on credit
booms and crises in economic history
Deirdre McCloskey on How we got rich
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)